necessity
A person acts out of necessity -
and
her conduct is therefore lawful - if she acts in
the protection of her own or somebody else's life, physical integrity,
property or
other legally recognised interest which is endangered by a threat of
harm which
has already begun or is immediately threatening and which cannot be
averted in
any other way; provided that the person who relies on the necessity is
not legally
compelled to endure the danger, and the interest protected by the act of
defence is
not out of proportion to the interest threatened by such an act.
Although this definition does not cover every
aspect of this ground of
justification,
it does contain the most important elements.
Private
defence and necessity distinguished
The two grounds of justification known as
necessity and private defence are
closely related. In both cases the
perpetrator (X in the examples which follow)
protects interests which are of value to
her, such as life, physical integrity and
property, against threatening danger. The
distinctions between these two
grounds of justification are the
following:
(1) the origin of the situation of
emergency: Private defence always stems from an unlawful (and therefore human) attack;
necessity, on the other hand, may stem either from an unlawful human act, or
from chance circumstances, such as natural occurrences.
(2) the object at which the act of
defence is directed: Private defence is always directed at an
unlawful human attack; necessity is directed at either the
interests of
another innocent third party or merely amounts to a violation of a
legal provision. The following
are examples of situations in which X's conduct is justified because
she is
acting in a situation of necessity:
(1) While X is in Y's backyard, Z attacks
her (X) with a knife. X finds herself
unable to ward off the attack, because
she (X) is slightly built and unarmed
whereas Z is strong and armed with a
knife. There is one possible way to
escape, and that is to kick a part of the
fence (which belongs to Y) to pieces
and then run away through the broken
fence. This is exactly what X then
does. If X is subsequently charged with
malicious injury to property in that
she broke a fence belonging to Y, she can
successfully rely on the defence of
necessity. In this example, the emergency
situation arose from an unlawful
act, but the act of defence is directed
not against the attacker, but against the
interests of an innocent third party,
namely Y.
(2) The facts of Goliath 1972 (3) SA 1
(A) are as follows: Z orders X to kill Y, and
threatens to kill X if she does not carry
out the order. There are no means of
escape for X, and she kills Y. X was
found not guilty. This type of situation is
known as ``compulsion'' or ``coercion''.
(3) The ship on which X is a passenger
sinks during a gale. X ends up in the ocean, clinging to a piece of driftwood.
Another former passenger, Y, clings to the same piece of wood. However, the two
of them are too heavy to be
kept afloat
by the wood. X pushes Y into the ocean in order to save her own
life.
Here the reason for the emergency was an act of nature and the act of
defence was
directed against an innocent person.
(4) The facts in Pretorius 1975 (2) SA 85
(SWA) are as follows:
X's
baby swallows
an overdose of Disprin
tablets. X rushes the child to the hospital by car for
emergency treatment. While driving to the
hospital, he exceeds the speed
limit. On a charge of exceeding the speed
limit he relies successfully on the
defence of necessity. Here, strictly
speaking, the reason for the situation of
emergency was a series of chance
circumstances; the act committed out of
necessity was directed not against some
person's interests, but amounted
merely to a violation of a legal
provision, namely the prohibition on speeding.
If X
acts in a situation of necessity, she acts lawfully.
Absolute and relative compulsion
In the case of absolute compulsion (vis
absoluta), X
does not commit a voluntary
act: for
example, Z, who is much stronger than X, grabs X's hand which is holding
a knife,
and stabs Y. The reason for X's non-liability is then not necessity, but the
absence of an
act (as this term is understood in law).
In the case of relative compulsion (vis
compulsiva)
there is indeed a voluntary action the part of X: Y threatens to kill X if X
does not kill Z. In this case, X is free to choose to be killed herself. Only cases of
relative compulsion may amount to situations of
necessity.
Requirements for a plea of
necessity
(1) legal interest threatened
(2) may also protect
another
(3) emergency already
begun but not
yet terminated
(4) may rely on necessity even if
personally responsible for emergency
(5) not legally compelled to
endure danger
(6) only way to
avert danger
(7) conscious of
fact that emergency exists
(8) not more harm caused
than
necessary
(these requirements are explained
into detail in your books)
Killing
another person out of necessity
Possibly the most perplexing question
relating to necessity as a ground of justification is
whether a threatened person may kill another in order to escape
from the
situation of emergency. Naturally, this question arises only if the
threatened person
finds herself in mortal danger. This mortal danger may stem
from compulsion,
for example where Y threatens to kill X if X does not kill Z, or
from an
event not occasioned by human intervention, for example where two
shipwrecked persons
vie for control of a wooden beam which can keep only one
of them
afloat and one of them eventually pushes the other away in an attempt to
survive.
Until 1972, our courts usually held that
the killing of a person could not be justified by
necessity (Werner 1947
(2) SA 828 (A); Mneke 1961 (2) SA 240 (N) 243;Bradbury 1967
(1) SA 387 (A) 399).
Goliath 1972 (3) SA 1 (A),
The test to determine necessity is
objective
The question whether X's acts fell within
the limits of the defence of necessity must be
considered objectively, that is in the light of the actual facts, and not
according to
what X (at the time) took the facts to be. If she is not actually (that is
objectively) in
such a situation, but merely thinks that she is, she cannot rely on necessity
as a justification. If she merely thinks that she is acting out of necessity
and,
while thus mistaken, directs her action against another person's interests, her
action remains
unlawful, but she may escape liability because she lacks
culpability.
This will become clear in the course of the
discussion of culpability
further on,
more particularly in the discussion of the effect of mistake and of
awareness of
unlawfulness. Such a situation may be described as putative
necessity.
No comments:
Post a Comment